Connect with us

MAiD

Skiing down euthanasia’s slippery slope

Published

14 minute read

From the Macdonald Laurier Institute

By John Keown

Canada is on track to surpass the Netherlands.

When the Canadian Parliament legalized voluntary euthanasia (VE) and physician-assisted suicide (PAS) in 2016, at the behest of the Supreme Court, supporters of legalization doubtless hoped the new law and its operation would prove something of a poster child for the compassionate and controlled medical ending of life. Its critics, however, might now describe it as less like a poster child and more like the picture of Dorian Gray.

Whether the law should permit VE and PAS is one of the most important questions of social policy in developed countries. Here we will eschew the tendentious and misleading euphemisms “assisted dying” and “medical assistance in dying.” The law and professional medical ethics have always allowed doctors and nurses to “help people to die” by palliating symptoms, even if so doing foreseeably shortens life. What the new law permits is radically different: the intentional killing of patients and intentionally assisting them to kill themselves.

Moreover, the euthanasia law does not require that patients be “dying” or “terminally ill” in order (to employ further euphemisms) to be given the “medication” for such “treatment.” Policy makers should not disguise, or be complicit in disguising, the foundational nature of this moral, legal, medical, and social paradigm shift.

The Canadian experience with VE and PAS is of major relevance to the international debate. Does it support the assurances of legalization campaigners that these practices can be effectively controlled by the law and provide a “last resort” in the sort of “hard cases” involving patients who are (or who fear) dying in severe pain or discomfort – patients who are so regularly paraded before us by the mass media?

Or does it support the counter-argument that the appropriate answer to such pain and discomfort is the wider availability of quality palliative care, and that a relaxed law would not only fail to prevent mistake or abuse but would also prove a first step on a precipitous “slippery slope” to VE and PAS in an ever-widening range of cases?

The best body of evidence concerning the effects of legalization comes from the Netherlands, whose experience I have studied for 35 years.

The Dutch Supreme Court declared VE and PAS lawful in 1984. To justify this change, the Dutch invoked the doctor’s duty to relieve suffering, and the focus of discussion was the physical suffering of the dying. However, in 1994 the same court held that the requirement of “unbearable suffering” could be satisfied by an illness that was neither terminal nor even physical and was solely mental. (Whether the patient’s suffering was “unbearable” remains very largely a subjective matter decided by the patient.)

In 2016 the Dutch government proposed a further legal extension: to elderly folk with a “completed” life. And, if some patients still do not manage to meet the lax legal criteria for VE and PAS their doctors can, and do, advise them that there is the option of being medically palliated while they dehydrate themselves to death.

Lethal injections have even been extended to patients who are incapable of making a request. In 1996 the Dutch courts declared it lawful intentionally to kill disabled infants, such as those with spina bifida. And only last year, the government announced that euthanasia would be allowed for children between one and 12. In short, over the past 40 years the Dutch have clearly tumbled down euthanasia’s slippery slope. Their Belgian neighbours, who followed them in 2002 (the same year that Dutch legislation enshrining the pre-existing legal criteria came into force) are also on the skids.

Why does this happen? There are two explanations, one empirical, the other logical. The empirical explanation is that relaxed laws cannot effectively control VE and PAS in practice because the challenges of formulating, drafting, and enforcing proper safeguards are intractable. Common media references to “strict safeguards” in places like the Netherlands and Canada reflect journalistic ignorance rather than social reality.

The second explanation is logical. VE and PAS are, campaigners tell us, justified by (i) respect for patient autonomy and (ii) by the duty to relieve suffering. But if one buys their argument, euthanasia is also justified for competent patients who are suffering from chronic, not merely terminal, illness, and whether their suffering is physical or mental. Suffering is suffering, whether from terminal cancer or chronic arthritis or depression. Indeed, suffering from chronic illness, physical or mental, may last a lifetime, not merely a few weeks or months. And why exclude the perduring existential suffering that tragically blights the lives of so many lonely, elderly folk?

Why, moreover, exclude euthanasia for suffering patients such as infants who are incapable of requesting death (non-voluntary euthanasia or NVE)? The absence of patient autonomy does not cancel the doctor’s duty of beneficence.

The Dutch have, then, proved nothing if not logical, and it is surely only a matter of time until their law is formally extended to embrace the elderly who are “tired of life.”

And so, to Canada. It leaped onto the slope as a result of the Supreme Court’s ruling in Carter v. Canada in 2015, in which the court overruled its previous decision in Rodriguez v. British Columbia in 1993. Rodriguez was soundly reasoned, and its reasoning remains in line with the rejection of a right to VE and PAS by the highest courts in other common law jurisdictions including the United States, the United Kingdom, and Ireland. By contrast (as I explain in Euthanasia, Ethics and Public Policy), Carter may strike some as reading more like rationalization than reasoning and as an exercise in judicial activism that stains Canadian jurisprudence.

Here we will mention just one of its flaws: its endorsement of the crucial finding of the trial judge that the evidence from jurisdictions with VE and/or PAS showed that the risks of legalization can be very largely avoided by carefully designed, well-monitored safeguards. This finding bristled with problems, not least of which was that no jurisdiction had (or has) carefully designed, well-monitored safeguards.

In a subsequent and similar case in Ireland, three senior judges carefully reviewed the judgment of the trial judge in Carter. They unanimously rejected her finding, not least in view of the (undisputed) evidence from the Netherlands and Belgium of the striking extent of medical euthanasia without any explicit request from the patient.

I was called as an expert witness in Carter by the Attorney General of Canada. At the end of my day-long cross-examination in Vancouver by the late Joseph Arvay, Q.C., counsel for those challenging the law against VE and PAS, the judge asked me to reprise both the practical and logical slippery slope arguments that I have outlined above. I did so, using the evidence from the Netherlands, Belgium, and Oregon to demonstrate the lack of effective legal control, and the Dutch endorsement of infanticide to illustrate the logical slippery slope. (Indeed, the two leading ethics experts called by Mr Arvay had endorsed both voluntary and non-voluntary euthanasia in their published work.)

The judge nevertheless concluded that the evidence showed that VE and PAS could safely be legalized. As for the logical argument, she dismissed it as involving “speculation” and because the legal challenge was only to the legal prohibition as it affected competent patients! Her failure to join the dots was noteworthy. (My 2022 paper in the Cambridge Law Journal confirms the real, not speculative, nature of the logical argument.) The Supreme Court endorsed the judge’s several errors. It did so, moreover, without even the fig leaf of a single dissenting judgment.

And what have we (all too predictably) witnessed since 2016, when legislation accommodated the Supreme Court’s ruling? Even leaving aside the steep yearly increases in the number of medical killings, we have seen that the statutory requirement that the patient’s death be “reasonably foreseeable” need no longer be met; that euthanasia where the sole cause of suffering is mental illness has been approved (though its implementation has been delayed until 2027 to allow preparations to be made), and that further expansion of the law to include “mature” minors, and requests for euthanasia written in advance of incompetence, is on the cards. Not to mention the several reported cases involving vulnerable patients that raise unsettling questions about the operation of the law.

In 1994 a distinguished House of Lords Select Committee on Medical Ethics unanimously concluded that English law should not permit VE or PAS. The committee observed that the criminal law’s prohibition on intentional killing was the “cornerstone of law and of social relationships” that “protects each one of us impartially, embodying the belief that all are equal.”

The experience in Canada uncomfortably confirms what happens once a society abandons that historic, bright-line prohibition in favour of the competing and arbitrary notion that whereas some people have lives that are “worth living,” others would be “better off dead” and it is right to grant their request to be killed or to help them kill themselves.

It is surely only a matter of time until calls are made for the “benefit” of a hastened death to be conferred on people who are incapable of requesting it. Why “discriminate” against people who are suffering with, say, advanced dementia merely because they are incapable of requesting a lethal injection? Why deny them their rights under the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms? The enormous cost savings will lurk supportively behind the argument, like a gangster’s heavy.

In the Netherlands, euthanasia has been normalized to a significant degree. Far from being an exceptional practice in “hard cases” of “last resort,” it has come to be regarded largely as another healthcare option. Canada appears to be following suit. Professor Trudo Lemmens, the eminent Canadian health lawyer, has noted the “troubling normalization” of euthanasia in Canada where, he adds, “rights rhetoric” surrounding the issue has replaced evidence-based debate.

Thankfully, the concerning developments in Canada are now being ventilated in the public domain: in the media, both in Canada and abroad; in journals of lawmedicine and bioethics, and by the UN rapporteur on the rights of people with disabilities. It is telling that in the UK even campaigners for legalization are straining to distance themselves from the Canadian precedent.

In 40 years, the Dutch have slid down the slippery slope. In fewer than 10, Canada appears to be veritably skiing.

John Keown DCL (Oxon) is the Rose F. Kennedy Professor of Christian Ethics in the Kennedy Institute of Ethics at Georgetown University in Washington, DC. He previously taught medical law at the University of Cambridge. The second edition of his book Euthanasia, Ethics and Public Policy: An Argument Against Legalisation, described as “magisterial” by Lord Judge, the former Lord Chief Justice of England and Wales, was published by Cambridge University Press in 2018.

Todayville is a digital media and technology company. We profile unique stories and events in our community. Register and promote your community event for free.

Follow Author

International

28-year-old Dutch woman to be killed by assisted suicide after doctors deem her autism ‘untreatable’

Published on

28-year-old Dutch woman Zoraya ter Beek (YouTube Screenshot)

From LifeSiteNews

By Louis Knuffke

28-year-old Zoraya ter Beek plans to die by assisted suicide over her struggles with depression and mental illness, a trend which is increasing in The Netherlands.

A 28-year-old autistic woman is scheduled to die by assisted suicide in May in The Netherlands after struggling with depression and mental illness, with her psychiatrist telling her that her condition is untreatable and will never improve. 

Zoraya ter Beek, who does not suffer from any physical illness, has decided to end her life by assisted suicide after psychiatrists said they had exhausted any means of helping her deal with her mental illnesses, which includes borderline personality disorder, according to The Free Press. 

Her struggles with mental illness have prevented her from being able to finish school or start a career. 

READ: Canadian judge blocks imminent euthanasia death of 27-year-old autistic woman 

In testimony to the nihilistic attitude adopted in the choice to end her own life on account of suffering, Ter Beek has decided that after she has been killed, her body will be cremated without a funeral and her ashes scattered in the woods. 

Ter Beek’s choice to take her own life comes despite her admitted fear of death arising from the uncertainty of what happens after death. 

“I’m a little afraid of dying, because it’s the ultimate unknown,” she said. “We don’t really know what’s next – or is there nothing? That’s the scary part.” 

The diagnosis of autism and mental illness as “untreatable” and “unbearable” has become an increasing trend in The Netherlands, with a study published in June 2023 revealing 40 cases over a 10-year period from 2012 to 2021. In a third of those cases, those with autism or intellectual disabilities were told there was no hope of improving their lives, and so their condition was deemed “untreatable.” 

Irene Tuffrey-Wijne, a palliative care physician at Britain’s Kingston University, who led the study  which examined 900 cases, said, “There’s no doubt in my mind these people were suffering. But is society really OK with sending this message, that there’s no other way to help them and it’s just better to be dead?” 

Tim Stainton, director of the Canadian Institute for Inclusion and Citizenship at the University of British Columbia, added, “Helping people with autism and intellectual disabilities to die is essentially eugenics.” 

The scheduled killing of the 28-year-old autistic woman comes as The Netherlands continues to expand the scope of what legally qualifies for euthanasia, with a new law effective February 1 allowing the killing of terminally ill children aged 1 through 12 who are deemed to be “suffering hopelessly and unbearably.” 

The law allows parents to decide to kill their child even if the child is unwilling or unable to consent. 

Continue Reading

Health

Quadriplegic man dies via euthanasia after developing bed sores waiting at Quebec hospital

Published on

66-year-old Quebec man Normand Meunier who died via euthanasia after a 4-day hospital stay left him with severe bed sores

From LifeSiteNews

By  Clare Marie Merkowsky

‘I don’t want to be a burden,’ the 66-year-old man said prior to his death after he developed bed sores due to a lack of specialized care at a hospital in Saint-Jérôme, Quebec.

A quadriplegic man in Quebec was killed via euthanasia after he developed severe bed sores while waiting in a hospital for an extended period of time. 

On March 29, Normand Meunier, a 66-year-old quadriplegic man in Quebec, was euthanized in his home after developing bed sores due to a lack of specialized care at the hospital in Saint-Jérôme, Quebec, according to a report by Radio-Canada. 

“I don’t want to be a burden. At any rate, the medical opinions say I won’t be a burden for long; as the old folks say, it’s better to kick the can,” Meunier told Radio-Canada in an interview the day before he was killed.  

Meunier, whose arms and legs have been paralyzed since 2022 due to a spinal cord injury, went to the hospital’s intensive care for a respiratory virus. According to his partner Sylvie Brosseau, the hospital placed Meunier on a stretcher for 95 hours.  

Bosseau revealed that she asked medical staff to provide a specialized bed for Meunier but was told that the hospital would have to order one. According to the hospital, they are investigating the incident, adding that they do have beds available.

After spending four days on a hospital cot, Meunier developed bed sores and a major pressure ulcer on his buttocks, which were so severe that the muscle and bone were exposed and visible. 

While Meunier had previously experienced bedsores, he determined to end his life via Medical Assistance in Dying (MAiD), the euphemistic name for Canada’s euthanasia regime, rather than continue to receive treatment.  

Unfortunately, Meunier is not the first Canadians to choose MAiD after being given insufficient medical care.  

This was the case of 52-year-old Dan Quayle, a grandfather from British Columbia. On November 24, he chose to be killed via lethal injection after being unable to receive cancer treatment due to the increased wait times.  

Throughout the agonizing wait, his family “prayed he would change his mind or get an 11th-hour call that chemo had been scheduled,” but were instead told consistently by the hospital that they were “backlogged.”  

Similarly, in 2022, a Winnipeg woman wrote in her posthumously published obituary that she chose to die by assisted suicide after being refused the treatments she needed: “I could have had more time if I had more help.”     

However, instead of supporting the healthcare system to prevent Canadians from taking their own lives, the Trudeau government is working to expand access to MAiD by loosening its requirements. 

On March 9, 2024, MAiD was set to expand to include those suffering solely from mental illness. This is a result of the 2021 passage of Bill C-7, which also allowed the chronically ill – not just the terminally ill – to qualify for so-called doctor-assisted death.    

After massive pushback from doctors, pro-life groups and politicians, the program’s expansion was temporarily paused until 2027.

According to Health Canada, in 2022, 13,241 Canadians died by MAiD lethal injection, which is 4.1 percent of all deaths in the country for that year, and a 31.2 percent increase from 2021. 

The number of Canadians killed by lethal injection since 2016 now stands at 44,958.  

Continue Reading

Trending

X